Messier 82

Messier 82
Beautiful Hubble shot of a starburst galaxy, M82
Showing posts with label pseudoscience. Show all posts
Showing posts with label pseudoscience. Show all posts

Friday, November 28, 2008

Bad Science and Bad Logic

I wrote an entry a few days ago praising the science reporting in the New York Times. But it seems that for every good pop-science article, there are a dozen bad ones. Take this latest from Discover Magazine as an example.

Science's Alternative to an Intelligent Creator: The Multiverse Theory

Now, I can't speak with authority on whether the scientists quoted in the article are doing bad science (improbable), or whether they're just terrible at communicating their good science (entirely possible), or whether the person who wrote the article simply misrepresented them horribly (most likely in my opinion). But I do know that the article is woefully misleading in both science and logic.

The article discusses the idea of the "multiverse," which is actually an interesting idea to contemplate. It proposes that there are many (possibly an infinite number of) other universes, which may have different physical laws than our own. Some variations of this theory include the proposition that other universes are continually spawning (possibly even from our own, through black holes or other oddities). Now, there are significant and legitimate arguments for the possible existence of a multiverse. The ones described in the article are not among them.

The authors try to tie the multiverse concept to another legitimate scientific idea: that the existence of the universe as we know it is highly improbable. It turns out that if you tweak certain parameters of our fundamental physical laws, life as we know it - along with other elements of the universe as we know it, such as stars, planets, etcetera - could not exist.

In the process, they commit at least two grievous logical errors which not only undermine their argument but could serve to discredit in the minds of the public the real, legitimate scientific theories which they are claiming to promote.

The first sin against logic is basing their argument on a highly-flawed understanding of probability. In essence, the argument is based on the idea that our universe's laws are highly improbable, but would be more probable if there were a bunch more universes out there. This argument is perhaps emotionally compelling, but it is in fact ridiculous.

It is true that when you play a game of chance a lot of times, it is in fact more likely that you will get a specific desired outcome one of the times. If I play the lottery ten million times, it is more likely that I will win one of those times than if I only play it once. This is basic probability, and most people have an intuitive understanding of it.

However (this is a big however), our intuition frequently leads us astray. The fact is that playing the game many times does not increase the odds of getting the specified outcome on any one specific play. Most of us intuitively believe that it does. It's normal, when playing at a slot machine, to think "I've lost so many times, I'm due to win any minute now!" Casinos base their profits on this intuitive misunderstanding. In reality (and casinos' profit margins operate in reality) the odds of winning the next time you play are completely unaltered by the fact that you lost the last 50 times you played.

This seems contradictory - doesn't playing more increase my chances of winning? Yes. But it doesn't increase my chances of winning at any one particular time. The converse is that knowing I've won on one particular play does not increase the probability that I've played a bunch of other times and lost. If I went out tomorrow, bought a lottery ticket, and won, you would not be able to reason from that outcome that I'd probably played the lottery hundreds or thousands or millions of other times.

How does this relate to the Discover article? The fact is that (assuming the laws of the universe arose by chance and not by some mechanism of necessity that we have yet to discover) all we know is that we've played the game at least once and won. We won this one specific time, and this specific universe has stars and planets and galaxies and life in it. If we had not won, we would not be here to argue about it, so it's guaranteed that in any universe where we exist to talk about it, we won. We can not deduce from that outcome how many times the game was played. It could have been played once, ten times, a thousand times, a million times, an infinite number of times, and none of those would alter the probability of this particular specific universe being the winning ticket. The probability of us being here, in this universe, right now, would be completely unchanged and would remain (again, assuming the laws we're talking about are a matter of chance) statistically infinitesmally small.

The second is invoking a false dichotomy. Here's the claim in the article:
Call it a fluke, a mystery, a miracle. Or call it the biggest problem in physics. Short of invoking a benevolent creator, many physicists see only one possible explanation: Our universe may be but one of perhaps infinitely many universes in an inconceivably vast multi­verse. Most of those universes are barren, but some, like ours, have conditions suitable for life.
Now, I don't know if they got this from the physicists. I certainly hope not. It lends credibility to two horrible anti-science arguments: first, that scientists are out to disprove the existence of a deity (and will go to any number of ridiculously absurd and illogical lengths to do so); second, that observations about the universe as we know it can be used as scientific evidence to point to the existence of a deity. Both of these arguments are patently false. Scientists in general are not hostile to religion and are not out to disprove it, and the fact that our universe is improbable is not an argument for the existence of an even more improbable entity.

Even barring the argument I made above from the discussion and assuming that the multiverse is actually a legitimate solution to the problem of the improbability of our universe (if it is a problem), this argument is still a false dichotomy.

First of all, for the same reason that intelligent design is not a solution to the problem of complexity, a divine or intelligent creator is not a solution to the problem of improbability. The creator/designer itself would have to be complex, and is certainly improbable - it would have to exist in the first place (how? we'll never know unless we can detect and measure it) and have a very specific set of characteristics in order to have created this specific universe as we know it.

Secondly, there are other possible solutions to the problem of improbability. Maybe there's something inherent to the process by which our universe formed that made its characteristics inevitable. Maybe there's something inherent to the stuff that comprises it. We don't know, and we're trying to find out. There are many potential solutions to this problem, and it is horribly disingenuous to point to two of them (neither of which is actually a solution) and claim that they're the only two.

Discover, I'm extremely disappointed in you.

Read more!

Wednesday, November 26, 2008

Science Basics: How Theories are Made, Part 2

So you've got your conjecture, and it appears to be consistent with observed reality. The next item on your agenda as a scientist is to decide whether or not your conjecture is within the realm of subjects that can be treated scientifically. There are many subjects that do not fit this description, and you should be aware of them now, before you go to all the trouble of trying to formulate a hypothesis and gather evidence.

Here are the questions you should ask yourself at this stage:

Do I have a solid grasp of the basic science underlying my idea?
Everything in science rests on the fundamental fields of physics, chemistry, and biology. If your exposure to one or more of these fields is limited to high school introductory courses, online reading and pop-science books, it would be an excellent idea to take a full year-long for-majors sequence of introductory courses in that science from a regionally-accredited college or university. It is best to make sure the physics course is calculus based; it is critical to do so if you will be working with physical science ideas. If you can identify the specific fundamental science with which you will primarily be working, it would not be a bad idea to take two different versions of the course, separated in space or time, so that you can be introduced to different viewpoints and ways of understanding the concepts. Most future scientists take an advanced course in their science in high school and then go on to take the introductory sequence at university.

To those who may feel a certain lack of trust in the scientific establishment: Please allow me to assure you that you can trust the content of these introductory courses. The science introduced here is truly fundamental, time-tested and solid. You will work in labs performing experiments to help demonstrate to yourself the validity of the theories presented. However, the entirety of human civilization is effectively a laboratory for these basic theories; these are the aspects of science to which we entrust our lives, our finances, and our precious memories on a daily basis. These are the theories on which airplanes, bridges, heart transplants, compact discs, electrical power systems, blood transfusions, antibiotics, computers, and food crops are built.

To young people and those without access to college courses: You can, of course, do some science without any formal education whatsoever. There are still a few unresolved questions of the sort that can be understood and worked with by high school students and interested laypersons, and there are any number of existing theories that could use some more experimental validation. And a great deal of the science involved in many interdisciplinary fields can be understood fairly well through dedicated self-study, provided that you have the capacity to read and understand introductory-level science textbooks. However, popular science books and the Internet will not provide an adequate background; you will need to seek out and work through books intended for students in the field.

Do I have a solid grasp of the basic mathematics used in science?
There are three basic types of mathematics used in science: algebra, calculus and statistics. The extent to which each of these is used, and the extent to which other types of math may be involved, depends on the specific variety of science. However, you will not be able to escape the need for math entirely. The math required for your introductory science courses or that which you find yourself needing to learn for your self-study program should be largely sufficient, with one exception: you will need to know some statistics to work with experimental data (yours or anyone else's).

Does my idea still fit with what I know about the world?
Now that you know some basic science and math, come back to your original idea. Is it still consistent with what you know about observed reality? If not, you may want to go back to the beginning and build a new conjecture, or you may want to refine your existing one so that it is consistent and possible. This is a personal decision that depends on the type of idea you're working with and how you feel about it.

Would I be satisfied if it turned out I were wrong?
This is a critically important question. Science does not prove positives; the best you can hope for is to gather a mountain of evidence to prop up your idea. It does, however, prove a whole lot of negatives. If you decide to enter your conjecture into the marketplace of scientific ideas, the odds are excellent that it will be partially or wholly disproven, modified, discarded, and/or replaced. At the rate that science has been moving in the last century, the odds are fairly good that this will happen within your lifetime. You should only consider treating your conjecture scientifically if you not only accept but look forward to this eventuality; in science, being "usefully wrong" is an accomplishment that helps humanity move forward in its journey toward understanding the universe more completely.

Can I formulate my conjecture in such a way that it makes measurable predictions?
It's okay to get stuck here for a while. What you're looking for is a formulation along the lines of:

"Under conditions (X, Y, Z...) outcome Q will be detected (more/less) often than would be predicted by (chance/existing theory)."
The "more/less often" part here is important. Your prediction doesn't have to be accurate every single time; it just has to beat the accuracy rate of either pure chance (if there's not currently a theory addressing the situation at hand) or the existing theory.

The observation that helium balloons and hot air rise in the Earth's gravitational field does not invalidate the theory that masses are attracted to other masses; it just means I've failed to identify a confounding variable (the Earth's atmosphere).

The observation that individuals with clearly maladaptive traits occasionally reproduce does not invalidate the theory of evolution by natural selection.

The observation that some years are cooler than previous years, or that some specific regions show a cooling trend, does not invalidate the theory that increased carbon dioxide in the atmosphere leads to increased average global surface temperatures.

If you've conjectured that some people are capable of telepathy, the fact that your telepath occasionally fails to accurately identify what another subject is thinking doesn't necessarily invalidate the whole idea (but you'll have to beat the accuracy rates predicted by both chance and current psychological theories of face/tone of voice reading, possibly by eliminating confounding variables by placing your subjects in different rooms).

As I said, it's fine to get stuck here. It will take some time to figure out what exactly it is that your conjecture might predict, what the current theories in the field are, what they predict, and how your predictions are different. Do be aware that it's perfectly fine (and usually desirable) for your conjecture to predict most or even all of the same things that current theories do, but it does have to set itself apart in some way. If it makes all the same predictions as the existing theory and no new ones, the only ways it can set itself apart are:
  1. by uniting and reconciling two conflicting theories (like the Standard Model of particle physics and general relativity). In this case, the theory would in fact make some predictions that differ from those made by each of the existing theories, although it's possible that it would make no new, unique predictions. This is what string theory is trying to do. However, it's struggling to gain acceptance, specifically because it's nearly impossible to validate it as the correct unification because it makes no new, unique predictions. (I'm oversimplifying, but that's the general gist of the problem)
  2. by being simpler and more elegant than the existing theory, while encompassing all of its predictions. This is, in theory, a nice sort of thing to develop. However, it turns out that when we make theories simpler and more elegant, they often do end up predicting more, because they're more generalized. Newton's laws of motion and universal gravitation were not only simpler, more elegant formulations of Kepler's laws of planetary motion, but also served to predict the motion of objects on Earth. So if you have a conjecture that's simpler and more elegant than the commonly-accepted theory, take a step back from it and look at things it might apply to outside of the realm of the current theory; odds are you'll find it's more general and does in fact make some new predictions.
Can I figure out a way to test my predictions?
This one can be tough too. The real world puts limits on what we can currently test. If the difficulty in testing your conjecture is purely technological - if you can imagine a way to test it if we had infinite energy, better telescopes, better microscopes, better brain imaging, better dating techniques, or fully-equipped zero-g labs - then you've probably got a testable hypothesis, and you should talk to other scientists about how you might be able to test it indirectly. If the difficulty is definitional - if it's built into the definition of your conjecture - then you may have a problem. Specifically, if you're postulating extra dimensions that can't be detected, beings that exist outside the observable universe, extrasensory perception that only works when the subject isn't being observed by scientists, or miracles that happened at some time in the past and left no physical evidence, you're probably dealing with a subject that science isn't equipped to handle.

Now, there are some cases where the difficulty in testing appears to be definitional but is actually technological. If you're predicting the existence of an invisible pink unicorn, it would seem that you'd have a definitional problem - but if your IPU has mass and leaves footprints, or if it's tangible, or if things slow down when they pass through it, and if you have a general idea of where to look for it, then it doesn't matter terribly much that it's invisible except when you're trying to demonstrate that it's pink. This is the case with physicists' search for dark matter, a subject about which we appear to maybe possibly be getting some direct evidence in recent months.

Congratulations! You've got a testable hypothesis!
If you've made it past all those hurdles, your conjecture is now a testable hypothesis. You know the background science, you know what your idea predicts, you know how to test your predictions, and you're ready to go check them against reality! On to Part 3: The Infinite Degrees of Wrong.

Read more!

Tuesday, November 25, 2008

Science Basics: How Theories are Made, Part 1

There's a lot of confusion going around when it comes to scientific theories. The very first comment I got on my very first substantive blog entry serves to illustrate that fact. While the folks talking about things like climate change or evolution bear the brunt of the confused people, even such seemingly neutral subjects as particle physics attract people who believe that pseudoscience is somehow morally equivalent to science.

It's therefore necessary, every now and then, to have a basic discussion of what science is and isn't, and specifically what a theory is and isn't. While we all (hopefully) get a basic introduction to the scientific method in grade school, the hypothesis -> experiment -> analysis -> conclusion is a very simplified description of an extremely complex process, one that gets more and more complex as we deal with larger, smaller, or more complex systems.

The Beginning: Conjectures
Most scientific theories are born as conjectures of some sort. A conjecture is, essentially, a guess; it's an exercise in what's called "inductive reasoning," or making a generalization about a process or property based on observation of a specific aspect of it. There are a lot of ways of forming conjectures:
  • You can observe an object or event and make a conjecture about its nature, structure, or identity. For instance, I could observe that the moon is pale and lumpy and propose that it is made of green cheese.
  • You can make a prediction about the behavior of some general class of things, based on the behavior of a single member of that class. For instance, I could observe the behavior of helium balloons and propose that objects are repelled by gravitational fields.
  • You can make a prediction based on purely logical or mathematical reasoning from a known theory. For instance, I could propose that all objects in the universe obey Newton's laws of motion.
  • You can find an inconsistency in a known theory and postulate an explanation for it. For instance, I could propose that the Arctic ice cap is melting faster than predicted because magma is leaking into the Arctic ocean.
  • You can run a computer model or simulation and make a prediction of the behavior of the system it models.
  • And there are probably dozens of other ways to come up with your conjecture. There isn't really an invalid way to do this; whatever works for the specific problem you're trying to solve is fine.
The key feature of a conjecture is that it's formulated as a possibility. It may or may not conform to observed reality; it may or may not have any supporting data; it may or may not be contradicted by some existing data. Conjectures are probably the closest thing in science to the meaning of the word "theory" in common speech. If you ever hear the phrase "I have a theory that," chances are you're dealing with a conjecture. UFO claims, predictions based on religious texts, and all the myriad claims of ESP, magic, time travel, extra dimensions, and the like all fall under this umbrella. So do many proposals by scientists, including (at this stage) the mathematical-physics construct called string theory, which is a perfectly good theory in the field of mathematics but rises only to the level of conjecture in the world of science. It's a big umbrella.

Once you've got your conjecture, the first thing you must do is ensure that it conforms with what you have already observed. All of the ones I proposed in the bullet list would fail this test. However, it's not terribly difficult to come up with ideas that might pass it, if you tweak them a little bit.

Next up: Part 2, Hypotheses and Testability.

Read more!